10, 03, 09
Hello again.
Just a reminder that the final essay is due after the Easter break, on
21st April. You just need to make sure that you select an essay
title from the SE4101 list if the essay you have recently handed in was from
the SE4102 list, and vice-versa. I’ve marked your essays and will hand them
back this Friday 13th March, between 10 o’clock and midday .
This week’s opinion piece
It’s on speciesism in the moral
sphere:
Most of us wish to live morally, conducive to which is that we should either
be good or avoid getting caught. What is totally unfair, I think, is that only
we humans are expected to show the self-restraint that being good requires, the
essence of which is consideration for other people unless they hit you first. When
it comes to other species, they can behave as badly as they like without
incurring our disapproval, as is graphically illustrated by a very distressing
personal experience of mine. I was on a train with a beatitude of nuns – this being
the collective term for them – when all at once a gang of chimpanzees burst
into our carriage and proceeded to create utter chaos and mayhem. They were as
common as could be, excreting and playing with themselves while shrieking and
jabbering; some hung upside down from the luggage racks and leered at the
sisters or smacked their lips, their own, not the sisters’, and one even sat on
the mother superior’s head and snatched her beads away. I was so incensed by this
outrageous behaviour that I closed the philosophy book I was reading, but the
mother superior just smiled at me and said that God loves all creatures, even
the most disruptive of them. Just imagine, I said, if a gang of football
hooligans had behaved like that, hanging naked upside down and so on; I don’t
think you would have been so tolerant then, I said, and very likely you would
have complained to the police and had them arrested.
This only goes to show that there is rampant discrimination against
human beings with regard to what counts as acceptable behaviour, other species
being given far more latitude than we give ourselves. I well remember how
shocked I was when I saw my first TV nature programme; it showed the wildlife
of the Serengeti National Park , and it was the first time
I had ever seen lions or zebras. I was thinking how pretty they all were when
all at once I found myself witnessing the most shocking scenes. One minute the
zebras were grazing peacefully and the lions were playing with their cuddly
little cubs, and the next minute I could hardly believe my eyes when the mother
lions launched a completely unprovoked attack on the zebras and actually jumped
on one of them and started biting and scratching it; and then, unbelievably, they ate it.
This crime was watched by millions of people, and the camera crew were
witnesses at the scene, as was the presenter, David Attenborough; and yet, not
a single one of those lions has been arrested or even brought in for
questioning. They are still at large and have not even had their cubs taken
away from them and put into care, despite the violent and anti-social behaviour
of the parents, which no doubt is being passed on to the next generation. If it
is morally wrong for people to kill and eat one another, then surely the same
is true for other animals.
This week’s joke:
A linguistics professor was lecturing to his class one day. ‘In
English’, he said, ‘a double negative forms a positive. In some languages,
though, such as Russian, a double negative is still a negative. However, there
is no language in which a double positive can form a negative.’
A voice from the back of the room piped up, ‘Yeah, right.’
Discussion topic
Here are last week’s notes on Singer’s environmentalism:
Chapter 10 of Practical Ethics is devoted to concern
for the environment. Singer considers the different values involved in the
debate about whether or not to build a hydro-electric dam in an area of
unspoilt wilderness. He says:
In general we
can say that those who favour building the dam are valuing employment and a
higher per capita income for the state above the preservation of wilderness, of
plants and animals…, and of opportunities for outdoor recreational activities.
(page 265)
According to
Singer the traditional western attitude to nature is anthropocentric, which is
to say that nature is valued only for the benefit it confers on our species.
Even within this tradition, he says, strong arguments may be deployed in favour
of preserving the environment, both with regard to direct benefits and with
regard to recreational use and the appreciation of nature. For instance, our
concern about global warming and climate change is based on human
self-interest, the danger to other species being of secondary importance. And
if such interest includes the pleasure we derive from contact with nature – he
gives the example of trekking through pristine forest – then a strong case can
be made for rejecting the proposal to build a dam.
These arguments
gather strength from considering not just our own interests but those of future
generations; and this is the case, he says, even if we allow for the
possibility that those not yet born will turn away from the appreciation of
nature in favour of living in a completely artificial environment. This is to
envisage that present trends will continue, for it is already the case that
many urban dwellers worldwide have no direct contact with wilderness areas.
Indeed, it could be argued that we in Britain (Singer is Australian) have no
access to truly wild areas, with the exception of Cardiff City Center on a
Saturday night, and that it makes little difference whether we live in town or
in the country. The British countryside, after all, is as much a product of
human design as is any suburban garden – it’s just bigger. There is a point
here that I shall pick up on later; for the moment, we need only remind
ourselves that for Singer the lives of future generations will be impoverished
if they cease to appreciate the wild places of the world. And he believes, as
we have seen, that human self-interest dictates that hydro-electric dams should
not be built in wilderness areas, the short-term economic gains being
outweighed by the long-term benefit, if future people are considered, of
preserving such places in their unspoilt state.
Having made that
point, he now asks whether the interests of non-human forms of life should also
be placed in the scales when weighing up the factors in favour of preservation.
His thesis, as we know, is that sentient creatures have intrinsic value, and
for that reason he thinks that we must also consider the interests of the
animals who occupy the particular area that it is proposed to develop, if such
development would damage or destroy their natural habitat. He draws the line,
however, at investing non-sentient forms of life with intrinsic worth, and at
this point he parts company with the holistic environmental ethics of those who
argue that trees and flowers have intrinsic worth and should be preserved for
their own sake. There is even a radical point of view which claims that
inanimate nature has intrinsic value, so that the landscape itself should be
preserved for its own sake. But Singer can make little sense of this, and
perhaps has no need to, for he would argue, I think, that rocks and ravines and
rivers and mountains should be preserved in order that we and those who come
after us may continue to enjoy them.
Let us turn, very
briefly, to an evaluation of Singer’s views. I said that I would pick up on
what was said earlier, and it concerned the lack of any truly wild places in Britain . It
seems doubtful to me that we are thereby impoverished, as Singer seems to imply
that we should be, and the reason, I think, is that the British countryside,
tame and manicured as it is, still manages to satisfy out desire for contact
with nature. If that desire is partly aesthetic, then many people would say
that the British countryside is beautiful, once the chemical sprays have
cleared away from the fields, and perhaps they would even go further and say
that an ordinary suburban garden can also be a thing of beauty, and that working
in a garden fulfils a need for contact with nature. So it may be, I suggest,
that we adjust our desires in order to bring them into line with opportunities
for satisfying them, and it would then make sense that we satisfy our desire
for contact with nature by gardening, or by going for a county ramble rather
than trekking through the Australian wilderness –– or even by strolling in the
local municipal park, with its greenery and its flower borders. The point here
is that people are adaptable, and one wonders whether Singer has overlooked
this in his insistence that the appreciation of nature requires the
preservation of wilderness.
What is clear from
this outline of Singer’s environmentalism is that it owes a great deal to what
he sees as our obligation to future generations. And yet, he makes very little
attempt to argue in support of our having such an obligation, which instead he
seems to take for granted, perhaps because he assumes that we would all agree
with him. He may be right, but I still think that a discussion is needed.
Is there, perhaps, a utilitarian basis for
such an obligation? We know, after all, that a utilitarian would consider a
person’s future interests, and we also know that for Singer it is essential to
being a person that one should be able to take the future into account and
expect one’s future desires to be satisfied. But there is a difference between
the future interests of a present person and those of future generations, and
it may be that this difference is relevant to the question of obligation. To
see whether it is, we could perhaps consider an intermediate situation: that in
which a person is not yet born but at some time can expect to be, or could
expect to be if, as a foetus, it were capable of expectation. We know that Singer
is in favour of abortion in certain circumstances, consistent with which is his
rejection of the argument that a foetus or embryo has a right to life because
it is potentially a person, with all that this implies about its possible
future happiness. It would follow from that argument, as he points out in
rejecting it, that contraception would be tantamount to abortion, since in both
cases one destroys a potential person.
But now, I think
we have to ask whether Singer is guilty of inconsistency here, for if the
potential for happiness of a foetus is of no account, then why should we
consider the potential for happiness inherent in the possibility of there being
future generations? Perhaps Singer would argue that it is more to do with
unhappiness than happiness. After all, we have a duty to consider the likely
future suffering involved in allowing a severely damaged foetus to go to term,
and it is very often in order to prevent such suffering that abortions are
carried out. Similarly, or so the argument goes, we have a duty with regard to
future generations to prevent the suffering that our present actions will cause
if we continue to vandalize the planet.
But then, why does
he not consider the possibility of terminating the human race? We know that
future people, if we allow them to exist, will be sad and miserable because of
global warming, which it is very unlikely that we are going to be able to bring
under control. We can prevent that suffering by outlawing human procreation,
with enforced abortion as the penalty for those who break the law. In that way
we can prevent all the suffering which otherwise will cascade down the
generations, just as we now prevent individual suffering by killing a damaged
foetus.
Another
possibility is that of compulsory sterilization of all newborn babies in order
to bring about the gradual extinction of the human race. One advantage would be
that at least the present generation would experience all the joys of
childbirth and nappy-changing, even if their sterilized adult children were
themselves unfulfilled as parents. This might seem to be a severe emotional
hardship, but keep in mind that if childlessness were universal, then its
effects would be mitigated by just this fact of being universally experienced,
so that childless couples would not be made unhappy by seeing parents cooing to
their babies or smacking their children in supermarket aisles.
Why is it, then,
that Singer makes no mention of such possibilities as a solution to the problem
of the future unhappiness of humankind? The reason, surely, is that he is also
concerned with their happiness, and in fact he writes of saving wilderness
areas for the enjoyment of future people.
But these are
people who do not yet exist and may never be born, depending on what we now do
and on whether, for example, we decide to have children. Similarly, a foetus is
only potentially a person and may never be born, depending, for example, on
whether the decision is made to abort it. According to Singer this potential is
not a reason to decide against abortion, though the likelihood of future
suffering is a reason to decide in favour of it. Should not the same apply to
our approach to future generations? If so, then we are not duty-bound to ensure
their existence, and if it is likely that their lives will be blighted by
misery because of global warming, or for some other reason, then perhaps we
should consider terminating the human race itself. It would then be left to
nature to re-colonize our roads and cities and universities, eventually to
obliterate them. And the good news, at least for Singer and the
environmentalists, is that the wilderness will flourish, albeit with no-one
left alive to appreciate it.
Second discussion topic
The empiricism
of John Locke
Locke was one of
the founders of empiricism, which is the doctrine that all knowledge of the
physical world derives from experience. It is then arguable that this is true
of all knowledge, whether of the physical world or not, at least if an
exception is made of logic and mathematics. This contrasts with, for instance,
the approach of Plato, whose epistemology (theory of knowledge) is bound up
with his theory of forms, which is a metaphysical theory far removed from our
everyday experience of the world. Empiricism may also be contrasted with the
views of Descartes, for whom knowledge of the world, or at least the
justification of what we know, is based on principles of reason, as with his
appeal to the revelatory force of clear and distinct ideas. Thus, an
ontological argument of his is that we have a clear and distinct idea of God as
a perfect being, who must therefore exist, since existence is intrinsic to
perfection.
Locke was not
consistently empiricist, as shown by his acquiescence in revealed religion, in
which respect his views coincided with Descartes’. Still, there are important differences,
and these are such as to mark out empiricism as a separate school of
philosophy, the founders of which were Locke, Berkeley and Hume.
As is well known,
Locke distinguishes between primary and secondary qualities with regard to the
senses. The primary qualities are those in which the objective physical
existence of an object resides; they are solidity, extension, shape and motion.
The secondary qualities are colours, sounds, smells, tastes – in other words
those features of an object which seem to belong as much to the perceiver as to
the object itself. This distinction has been called into question: surely the
shape of an object, for instance, is as hard to categorise as being objective
or subjective as is its colour. Still, the distinction at least draws attention
to a genuine problem of analysis.
Preparation for
next week
Some of the
remaining Monday lectures are about the philosophy of David Hume, which is
likely, therefore, to figure in the exam questions, as well as being one of the
essay topics. Let’s start with his theory of mind.
He says that
simple ideas are based on the simple impressions which cause them, as when the
experience of looking at colours gives rise to fainter ideas in the form of
memories of colours or coloured objects; also, to coloured images of imagined
objects.
Taking this
approach, Hume would say, for instance, that a congenitally blind person cannot
picture colours, or that a congenitally deaf person cannot imagine sounds, for
instance by having a tune running through his or her head. This would seem to
be a factual claim; as such, I do not know whether it is true.
Hume now goes
further by tying ‘ideas’ to understanding and meaning, so that he would say,
for instance, that a congenitally blind person cannot understand colour words.
In order to comment on this, let’s assume that such people are not able to
imagine colours, for instance the colour red; does it follow that they cannot
understand the word ‘red’? Isn’t such understanding a matter of degree? If so,
then a blind person may know that red is a colour, that colour is a property of
the physical objects that he or she can detect with other senses, that ‘red’ is an adjective and ‘redden’ is a verb,
that blood and tomatoes and sunsets are red, that the colour red is associated
with rage and passion. That seems to be quite a lot of understanding for
someone who does not understand ‘red’. What do you think? Or would you say that
experience of the actual colour is essential to the concept of red?
Is there really
such a thing as a simple impression in Hume’s sense? Well, I could wake up in a
world of blue; not a blue wall or blue sky, but just the colour blue all around
me and through me. At the same time, perhaps other senses more easily receive
simpler impressions than sight does. It is easy to imagine pure smell, not
associated with any physical object as its source, or the pure sensation of
cool water on hot skin. So, yes, there would seem to be simple impressions; but
the world’s furniture is made up of complex physical objects such as chairs. Is
one’s concept of a chair derived from simple impressions? But all one’s senses
have contributed to that concept – well, perhaps not the sense of taste, unless
you find licking a chair easier than flicking around it with a duster.
The point, anyway,
is that it is by no means clear that one’s ‘idea’ of a chair is exclusively
derived from sense-impressions; on the other hand, it could be argued that if I
were congenitally blind, deaf, unable to taste or smell or feel sensations
through my skin, then my understanding of the world would be somewhat limited,
perhaps to the extent that I would have no concept of a chair or even of a
bench.
Answer to last
week's puzzle
Here it is again:
The Dollar
bills
In a bag are
26 bills. If you take out 20 bills from the bag at random, you have at least
one 1-dollar bill, two 2-dollar bills, and five 5-dollar bills. How much money
was in the bag?
If you have at least one 1-dollar bill, you
would have one if the six bills left in the bag were all 1-dollar bills. So
there are seven 1-dollar bills. Do the same for the other denominations. The
answer then turns out to be 78 dollars.
This Week's Puzzle
A map of the red planet displays
newly discovered cities and waterways. Start at the city T on the south pole.
Travelling along the canals, visiting each city only once and returning to the starting point, can you spell out a sentence in English?
Travelling along the canals, visiting each city only once and returning to the starting point, can you spell out a sentence in English?
This problem, by the prolific
American puzzle inventor Sam Loyd, is more than a hundred years old.
He wrote that ‘when the puzzle originally appeared in a magazine, more than fifty thousand readers reported “There is no possible way.” Yet it is a very simple puzzle.’ You will kick yourself if you read the answer before you work it out.
He wrote that ‘when the puzzle originally appeared in a magazine, more than fifty thousand readers reported “There is no possible way.” Yet it is a very simple puzzle.’ You will kick yourself if you read the answer before you work it out.
Comments
Post a Comment